Does telling white lies signal pro-social preferences? (2024)

Does telling white lies signal pro-social preferences?

Judgment and Decision Making, Vol.10, No.6, November 2015, pp. 538-548

Laura Biziou-van-Pol*Jana Haenen*Arianna Novaro*Andrés Occhipinti Liberman*Valerio Capraro#

The opportunity to tell a white lie (i.e., a lie that benefits another person) generates a moral conflict between two opposite moral dictates, one pushing towards telling the truth always and the other pushing towards helping others. Here we study how people resolve this moral conflict. What does telling a white lie signal about a person’s pro-social tendencies? To answer this question, we conducted a two-stage 2x2 experiment. In the first stage, we used a Deception Game to measure aversion to telling a Pareto white lie (i.e., a lie that helps both the liar and the listener), and aversion to telling an altruistic white lie (i.e., a lie that helps the listener at the expense of the liar). In the second stage we measured altruistic tendencies using a Dictator Game and cooperative tendencies using a Prisoner’s dilemma. We found three major results: (i) both altruism and cooperation are positively correlated with aversion to telling a Pareto white lie; (ii) both altruism and cooperation are negatively correlated with aversion to telling an altruistic white lie; (iii) men are more likely than women to tell an altruistic white lie, but not to tell a Pareto white lie. Our results shed light on the moral conflict between prosociality and truth-telling. In particular, the first finding suggests that a significant proportion of people have non-distributional notions of what the right thing to do is, irrespective of the economic consequences, they tell the truth, they cooperate, they share their money.


Keywords: lying-aversion, white lies, cooperation, altruism, prosociality, moral dilemmas.

1Introduction

Moral decision-making in communication often concerns the choice whether to tell the truth or to deceive. While it is generally agreed that it is bad to tell lies that increase your benefit at the expense of that of another person (black lies), moral philosophers have long argued about if and when telling a lie that increases the benefit of another person (white lie) is morally acceptable. We find Socrates pointing out to one of his interlocutors in Plato’s Republic that, “when any of our so-called friends are attempting, through madness or ignorance, to do something bad, isn’t it a useful drug for preventing them?”—suggesting that, given the circ*mstances, deception might be the “good” thing to do (Plato [1997]). At the other end of the spectrum we find Immanuel Kant, for whom good intentions or consequences cannot justify an act of lying. For Kant, telling even a white lie is “by its mere form a crime of a human being against his own person and a worthlessness that must make him contemptible in his own eyes.” (Kant [1996]).

This raises the question whether prosocial agents would tell such “useful” lies, or condemn them, as Kant did. Prosocial behaviour, that is, behaviour intended to benefit other people or society as a whole, is widely considered the right course of action in situations in which there is a conflict between one’s own benefit and that of others. The Golden Rule, which encapsulates the essence of prosociality, is indeed “found in some form in almost every ethical tradition” (Blackburn [2003]). Thus, a prosocial person, when facing the decision of whether to tell a white lie or not may experience a conflict between two diverging moral dictates, one pushing towards lying for the benefit of others and the other pushing towards telling the truth regardless of circ*mstance.

Since most human interaction revolves around communication and involves some degree of prosociality, understanding how this conflict is resolved is not only interesting from the theoretical point of view of moral philosophy, but also from a more practical point of view. For instance, taking verbatim an example from Erat and Gneezy [2012] “should a supervisor give truthful feedback to a poorly performing employee, even when such truthful feedback has the potential to reduce the employee’s confidence and future performance?” What does telling a white lie signal about the supervisor’s prosocial tendencies?

The focus of the present paper is on this type of question and, more generally, the moral conflict between lying aversion and prosocial behaviour.

To measure prosocial tendencies and aversion to telling white lies webuild on previous studies in behavioural economics, which placeeconomic games into experimental settings. Specifically, the DictatorGame (DG), due to its setup, has proven useful in measuring altruisticproclivities in recruited subjects. In a standard DG, one player (thedictator) is given an initial endowment and is asked to decide howmuch of it, if any, to transfer to a passive player (the recipient),who is given nothing. The anonymity and confidentiality of decisionsare ensured to rule out incentives (such as reputation) to share theirendowment with the recipient. Although the theory of hom*o œconomicus predicts that dictators keep the whole endowment forthemselves, research has shown that a significant proportion ofdictators allocate a non-trivial share to recipients (Camerer [2003],Engel [2011], Forsythe et al. [1994], Kahneman et al. [1986]).

Akin to the manner in which the DG is used in research as the paradigmatic game with which toinvestigate altruism, extensive use has been made of the Prisoner’sDilemma (PD) in experimental settings in order to investigatecooperative behaviour in agents. In the standard one-shot two-playerPD, both players can either cooperate or defect. If a playercooperates, he pays c and bestows b>c on the other player while,if he defects, he pays and gives 0. Clearly hom*o œconomicuswould defect in any case since, irrespective of the strategy of the other,the optimal strategy is to give 0. Yet in day-to-day life people often docooperate and, perhaps unsurprisingly, research has shown that even inanonymous one-shot PD experiments a significant percentage of people choose tocooperate (see, e.g., Rapoport [1965]).

More recently, behavioural scientists have delved into choices peoplemake regarding deception in different circ*mstances and underdifferent conditions. Unlike cooperation and altruism, lying aversionis not measured by a unique and standard economic game and (at least)three different models have been put forward (Gneezy etal. [2013]). However, irrespective of the model used, findings allpoint to the same direction: while the classic approach in economicsassumes that people are selfish and that lying in itself does notinvolve any cost, accumulating evidence suggests that a significantamount of people are lie-averse in economic and social interactions(Abeler et al. [2014], Cappelen et al. [2013], Erat and Gneezy[2012], Gneezy [2005], Gneezy et al. [2013], Hurkens and Kartik[2009], Lundquist et al. [2009], Weisel and Shalvi [2015]).

Recent research has also shed light on when people are more likely to use deception. Shalvi et al. [2011] find that “observing desired counterfactuals attenuates the degree to which people perceive lies as unethical”. Wiltermuth [2011] finds that people are more likely to cheat when the benefit of doing so is split between themselves and another person, even when the other beneficiary is a stranger with whom they had no interaction.Gino et al. [2013] distinguish among the mechanisms that may drive this increased willingness to cheat when the spoils are split with others. They suggest that the ability to justify self-serving actions as appropriate when others benefit is a stronger driver for unethical behaviour than pure concern for others. They also find that people cheat more when the number of beneficiaries increases and that individuals feel less guilty about their dishonest behaviour when others benefit from it.Conrads et al. [2013] examine the impact of two prevalent compensation schemes, individual piece-rates (under which each individual gets one compensation unit for each unit they produce) and team incentives (under which the production of the team is pooled and each individual receives one half of a compensation unit per unit of the joint production output). They find that lying is more prevalent under team incentives than under the individual piece-rates scheme. Thus, their results add to the evidence in Wiltermuth [2011] and Gino et al. [2013] suggesting that individuals are more willing to lie when the benefits of doing so are shared with others.Cohen et al. [2009] test whether groups lie more than individuals. They find that groups are more inclined to lie than individuals when deception is guaranteed to best serve their economic interest, but lie relatively less than individuals when honesty can be used strategically. Their results suggest that groups are more strategic than individuals in that they will use or avoid deception in order to maximise their economic outcome.

A few previous studies have investigated the relation between prosocial behaviour and aversion to telling white lies. Shalvi and de Dreu [2014] show that oxytocin, a neuropeptide known to promote affiliation and cooperation with others, promotes group-serving dishonesty. Levine and Schweitzer [2014] report that people who tell white lies are perceived as more moral than those who tell the truth. In a subsequent work, Levine and Schweitzer [2015] show that trusters in a trust game allocate more money to people who have told a white lie in a previous game than to people who have told the truth. This result provides evidence that telling a white lie signals prosocial behavior to observers. However, Levine and Schweitzer [2015] do not measure trustees’ behavior and thus it remains unclear whether those who tell white lies are really more prosocial than those who tell the truth. One corollary of the results of the current paper is that the answer to this question is positive in the case of altruistic white lies (those that benefit the other person at the expense of the liar), but negative in the case of Pareto white lies (those that benefit both the other person and the liar).

More closely related to our work is that of Cappelen et al. [2013], which explores the correlation between altruism in the DG and aversion to telling a Pareto white lie (PWL), providing evidence that people telling a Pareto white lie give significantly less in the Dictator Game. Our work builds on and extends the results of this paper.

Indeed, although these results represent a good starting point, more research is needed to develop a better understanding of the relation between aversion to telling a white lie and prosocial behaviour. First of all, most everyday situations are better modelled by a PD, rather than a DG. Since altruism in the DG and cooperation in the PD are different behaviours (virtually all altruistic people cooperate, but the converse does not hold - see Capraro et al. [2014a], it is also important to investigate the correlation between cooperation in the PD and aversion to telling a white lie. Second, many white lies are not Pareto optimal, but involve a cost for the liar (altruistic white lies, AWL). Thus, it is important to go beyond Pareto white lies and explore also the correlation between prosocial behaviour and altruistic white lies.

To fill this gap, we implemented a 2x2 experiment, in which subjects play a two-stage game. In the first stage they play one out of two possible treatments in a variation of the Deception Game introduced by Gneezy et al. [2013]. In these treatments they have the opportunity to tell either a Pareto or an altruistic white lie. In the second stage subjects are assigned to either the PD or the DG. We have evidence for three major results: (i) both altruism and cooperation are positively correlated with aversion to telling a Pareto white lie; (ii) both altruism and cooperationare negatively correlated with aversion to telling an altruistic white lie; (iii) men are more likely than women to tell an altruistic white lie, but not to tell a Pareto white lie.

2Experimental design and procedure

We set up a two-stage experiment in which we first collect data on subjects’ lying aversion; followed by data regarding their prosocial preferences. In the first stage, subjects were directed to one of two variations on the Deception Game, in the spirit of Gneezy et al. [2013]. One variation serves to measure aversion to tell an altruistic white lie; the other variation serves to measure aversion to tell a Pareto white lie. In the second stage of the experiment, the players were randomly assigned to either the DG or the PD. Comprehension questions were asked for each of the four games, before any decision could be made. Subjects failing any of the comprehension questions were automatically excluded from the survey. In the next subsections we describe the experimental design. Full experimental instructions are reported in Appendix A.

2.1Stage 1: Measure of lying-aversion

In the first stage of the experiment, subjects played a Deception Game akin to that of Gneezy et al. [2013] with Pareto White Lies (PWL) and Altruistic White Lies (AWL) treatments. As in Gneezy et al. [2013] two players are paired and the first player has the opportunity to tell a white lie. However, unlike Gneezy et al. [2013], in our Deception game the payoffs of both players depend only on Player 1’s choice and not on whether Player 2 believes that Player 1 is telling the truth or telling a lie. In our Deception Game, Player 2 is passive and does not make any decision. We use this variant because we are interested in looking at the relation between Player 1’s lying aversion and their prosocial tendencies. Our design allows us to avoid confounding effects due to the beliefs that Player 1 may have about the beliefs of Player 2. Since in our design Player 2 does not make any decision, the beliefs that Player 1 may have about Player 2 do not play any role and a prosocial Player 1 will always tell a white lie, regardless of their beliefs regarding Player 2.

Specifically, in our Deception Game, Player 1 is assigned to group i, where i∈{1, 2}. The group allocation is communicated only to Player 1. Player 1 can choose between two possible strategies. Option A: telling the number of the group they were assigned to; or Option B: telling the number of the other group. Players in the AWL condition were told that the payoff for each player would be determined as follows:

  • Option A: Player 1 and Player 2 earn $0.10 each.
  • Option B: Player 1 earns $0.09 and Player 2 earns $ 0.30.

Players in the PWL condition, on the other hand, were told that the payoff for each player would be determined as follows:

  • Option A: Player 1 and Player 2 earn $ 0.10 each.
  • Option B: Player 1 and Player 2 earn $ 0.15 each.

2.2Stage 2: Measure of prosociality

In the second stage of the game, all subjects were randomly assigned to either a one-shot anonymous Dictator Game (DG) or a one-shot anonymous Prisoner’s Dilemma (PD) to assess the extent of their altruism toward, or cooperation with, unrelated individuals.

In the DG, dictators were given an initial endowment of $ 0.20 and were asked to decide how much money, if any, to transfer to a recipient, who was given nothing. Each dictator was informed that the recipient they were matched with would have no active role and would receive only the amount of money the dictator decides to give. In the PD, subjects were given an initial endowment of $ 0.10 and were asked to decide whether to transfer the $ 0.10 to the other subject (cooperate) or not (defect). Each time a subject transfers their $0.10, the other subject earns $0.20. Each subject was informed that the subject they were matched with would be facing the same decision problem.

We deliberately chose to use the word ”transfer”, rather than “give”, “cooperate”, or similar words, in order to minimise possible framing effects caused by the moral weight associated with names of the strategies.

3Results

Subjects living in the United States were recruited via thecrowd-sourcing internet marketplace Amazon Mechanical Turk (Paolacciet al. [2010], Horton et al. [2011], Bartneck et al. [2015]). A totalof 1212 subjects (59% males, mean age = 33.83) passed thecomprehension questions and participated in our experiment.

In the first stage of the experiment, 614 subjects played in the AWL treatment while 598 subjects were assigned to the PWL treatment. Pareto white lies were told extremely more frequently than altruistic white lies: whilst only 23% of the subjects chose to tell an altruistic white lie, 83% of the subjects lied in the PWL treatment (Wilcoxon Rank sum, p < .0001). These results are qualitatively in line with those reported by Erat and Gneezy [2012], who found that 43% of people lie in their AWL treatment and 76% of subjects lie in their PWL treatment. The effect of demographic questions on lying aversion will be discussed separately.

In the second stage of the experiment, 697 subjects were assigned tothe DG, while 515 played the PD. Dictators on average transferred 22%of their endowment, whilst in the PD cooperation was chosen 35% ofthe time. Linear regression predicting DG donation as a function ofthe three main demographic variables (sex, age, and education level)shows that women donated more than men (coeff = 1.74, p < .0001),that older people donated slightly more than younger people (coeff=0.03, p=0.048) and that education level has no significant effecton DG donations (coeff = 0.04, p=0.78).1 On the other hand, logitregression predicting cooperation as a function of the three maindemographic variables shows that none of them has a significant effecton cooperative behaviour (all p’s >0.15).

3.1Altruism and lying-aversion

Figure 1 reports the average (normalized) DG donation of liars andhonests in both the AWL and the PWL treatments and suggests thathonest people were more altruistic than liars in the PWL treatment,but less altruistic than liars in the AWL treatment. To confirm thiswe use linear regression predicting DG donation using a dummyvariable, which takes value 1 (resp. 0) if the subject has toldthe truth (resp. a lie). Results show that, in the AWL treatment,honest people were almost significantly less altruistic than liars(coeff =−1.14, p = 0.063), and that, in the PWL treatment, honestpeople were significantly more altruistic than liars (coeff = 1.43,p = 0.035).

Next we examine whether these differences are predicted by individualdifferences in demographics. To do this, we repeat the linearregressions including controls on the three main demographic variables(sex, age, and level of education). Results show that, in the AWLtreatment, honest people were significantly less altruistic than liars(coeff =−1.33, p = 0.03), and that, in the PWL treatment, honestpeople were almost significantly more altruistic than liars (coeff = 1.26, p = 0.06). In both cases, the only significantdemographic variable is the gender of the subject (AWL: coeff= 1.74, p = 0.0008, PWL: coeff = 1.79, p = 0.0008). The fullregression table is reported in Appendix B, Table 1. Thus, althoughthe difference in altruism between liars and honest people is partlydriven by the gender of the subject, it remains significant orclose to significant also after controlling for this variable,suggesting existence of a true effect of aversion to telling a whitelie on altruistic behaviour in the Dictator Game.

Figure 1: Average (normalized) DG donation of liars and honests in both the AWL and the PWL treatments. Error bars represent the standard errors of the means. In the Pareto white lies treatment, honest people tend to me more altruistic than liars (linear regression with no control on socio-demographic variables: coeff = 1.43, p = 0.035; with control: coeff = 1.26, p = 0.06). In the altruistic white lies treatment, honest people tend to be less altruistic than liars (linear regression with no control on socio-demographic variables: coeff = −1.14, p = 0.063; with control: coeff = −1.33, p = 0.03).

Does telling white lies signal pro-social preferences? (1)

3.2Cooperation and lying-aversion

Figure 2 reports the average PD cooperation of liars and honests inboth the AWL and the PWL treatments and suggests that, as in the DGcase, honest people were more cooperative than liars in the PWLtreatment, but less cooperative than liars in the AWL treatment. Toconfirm this we use logit regression predicting PD cooperation using adummy variable, which takes value 1 (resp. 0) if the subject hastold the truth (as opposed to a lie). Results show that, in the AWLtreatment, honest people were much less altruistic than liars (coeff=−1.25, p < .0001), and that, in the PWL treatment, honest peoplewere significantly more altruistic than liars (coeff = 0.71,p = 0.04).

Next we examine whether these differences are driven by demographicdifferences. To do this, we repeat the logit regressions includingcontrols on the three main demographic variables. Results show that,in the AWL treatment, honest people were less altruistic than liars(coeff =−1.31, p < .0001), and that, in the PWL treatment, honestpeople were more altruistic than liars (coeff = 0.79, p =0.02).In both cases, none of the demographic variables is significant (onlygender has an almost-significant effect (p = 0.08), but only inthe PWL treatment). Full regression table is reported in Appendix B,Table 2.

Figure 2: Average PD cooperation of liars and honests in both the AWL and the PWL treatments. Error bars represent the standard errors of the means. In the Pareto white lies treatment, honest people tend to be more cooperative than liars (logit regression with no control on socio-demographic variables: = 0.71, p = 0.04; with control: coeff = 0.79, p = 0.02). In the altruistic white lies treatment, honest people tend to be less cooperative than liars (logit regression with no control on socio-demographic variables: coeff =−1.25, p < .0001; with control: coeff =−1.31, p < .0001).

Does telling white lies signal pro-social preferences? (2)

3.3Gender differences in deception

Gender differences in deceptive behaviour have attracted considerable attention since the work of Dreber and Johannesson [2008], who found that men are more likely than women to tell a black lie, that is, a lie that benefits the liar at the expense of the listener. In the context of white lies, Erat and Gneezy [2012] found that women are more likely than men to tell an altruistic lie, but men are more likely than women to tell a Pareto white lie. Interestingly, the latter result was not replicated by Cappelen et al. [2013], who found no gender differences in lying aversion in the context of Pareto white lies. In line with this latter result, we also find no gender differences in the PWL treatment. Indeed, logit regression predicting the probability of telling a Pareto white lie as a function of sex, age, and level of education shows no significant effect of gender (coeff = 0.25, p = 0.25) and age (coeff =−0.01, p = 0.47) and, if anything, shows a significant negative effect of the level of education (coeff =−0.18, p = 0.04). Interestingly, in the context of altruistic white lies, we even find the reverse correlation of that reported by Erat and Gneezy [2012]. In our sample, men are slightly more likely than women to tell an altruistic white lie (26% vs 18%). The difference is statistically significant as shown by logit regression predicting the probability of telling an altruistic white lie as a function of sex, age, and level of education (gender: coeff = 0.50, p=0.02; age: coeff =−0.00, p = 0.85; education: coeff =−0.02, p = 0.73). We refer the reader to Figure 3 for a visual representation of gender differences in deceptive behaviour.

Figure 3: Proportion of females across treatments divided between liars and honests. In the Pareto white lie treatment, there is no statistically significant gender difference in deceptive behaviour. On the other hand, in the altruistic white lie treatment, we found that women are significantly more likely than men to tell the truth.

Does telling white lies signal pro-social preferences? (3)

4Discussion

We conducted this experiment to explore the relation between cooperation, altruism, and aversion to telling white lies among subjects. Cooperative tendencies were measured through the Prisoner’s Dilemma (PD); altruistic tendencies were measured through the Dictator Game (DG); and lying-aversion was measured using a Deception Game. The setup of our Deception Game was such that if Player 1 chose to lie then there would be an increase in monetary outcome for both players (the Pareto white lie variant, PWL) or an increase in monetary outcome for Player 2 at a small cost to Player 1 (the altruistic white lie variant, AWL). Our design differed from previous versions of the Deception Game in that the payoffs of both players depend only on the decision of the first player. This design allows us to study the correlation between Player 1’s lying-aversion and prosocial tendencies without adding the potentially confounding factor that Player 1 may have beliefs about the behaviour of Player 2.

Our results provide evidence of three major findings: (i) both altruism and cooperation are positively correlated with aversion to telling a Pareto white lie; (ii) both altruism and cooperation are negatively correlated with aversion to telling an altruistic white lie; (iii) men are more likely than women to tell an altruistic white lie, but not to tell a Pareto white lie.

These results make several contributions to the literature. Thepositive correlation between altruism and aversion to telling a Paretowhite lie was also found by Cappelen et al. [2013]. Our resultsreplicate and extend this finding as they also show that the samecorrelation holds true when considering cooperative behaviour (asopposed to altruistic behaviour), and that these correlationsdisappear and are actually even reversed when considering altruisticwhite lies (as opposed to Pareto white lies). These are not trivialextensions. Indeed, a positive correlation between altruism in the DGand aversion to telling a Pareto white lie can, in principle, beexplained by assuming that there are two types of agents: (i)non-purely utilitarian agents, who aim at maximising the socialwelfare and choose the strategy that maximises their payoff in casemultiple strategies give rise to the same social welfare (e.g.,Charness and Rabin [2002],Capraro [2013]); and (ii) purelyegalitarian agents, who minimise payoff differences, irrespective oftheir own payoff (e.g., with suitable values for the parametersof the models, Fehr and Schmidt [1999]), Bolton and Ockenfels[2000]. Assuming this type distribution, non-purely utilitarianagents always tell Pareto white lies (because they increase thesocial welfare) and give nothing in the DG (because giving does notincrease the social welfare); and purely egalitarian agents givehalf in the DG, yet are indifferent between telling a Pareto whitelie or not in the Deception Game (since they both minimise payoffdifferences). Thus, if the proportion of utilitarian agents is largeenough, this would generate a positive correlation between altruismin the DG and aversion to tell a Pareto white lie, that would beconsistent with the findings in Cappelen et al. [2013].

On the other hand, explaining our results using distributional preferences is much harder. Indeed, to explain the negative correlation between cooperation in the PD and telling a PWL, one must assume that the majority of utilitarian people actually defect in the PD. But this assumption clashes with the very nature of utilitarian people—that of maximising the total welfare and thus cooperation in the PD.

One potential explanation for our findings is that subjects have two possible degrees of moral motivation (low or high) towards either of two moral principles (utilitarianism and deontology). Utilitarian people follow distributional preferences for maximising the social welfare; deontological people follow non-distributional preferences for doing what they think it is the right thing to do. We assume that these types of individuals act as follows:

  • High utilitarian people give half in the DG, cooperate in the PD, and lie in the AWL and in the PWL.
  • High deontological people give half in the DG, cooperate in the PD, and tell the truth in the AWL and in the PWL.
  • Low utilitarian people keep in the DG, keep in the PD, tell the truth in the AWL and are indifferent in the PWL.
  • Low deontological people keep in the DG, keep in the PD, tell the truth in the AWL and are indifferent in the PWL.

According to this partition, the positive correlation between truth-telling and DG-donation/PD-cooperation in the PWL treatment would be driven by high deontological subjects; and the negative correlation between truth-telling and DG-donation/PD-cooperation in the AWL treatment would be driven by low utilitarian and low deontological subjects.

There might be high utilitarian subjects as well, but they do not showup because we have only one case per subject. An interesting direction for future research is therefore to do a within-subject design with many trials, using different payoffs, aimed at establishing the position of each subject in a two-dimensional space.

Of course, more research is needed also to support the existence of apossibly non-distributional “deontological domain”, containing allthose actions that a particular individual considers to be morallyright independently of their economic consequences, and to classifythe actions belonging to this domain. For instance, here we havefocussed on altruism and cooperation, as they are the most studiedprosocial behaviours. However, they are not the only ones. Futureresearch may be devoted to understanding whether the same correlationswith truth-telling hold for other prosocial behaviours, such asbenevolence (i.e., acting in such a way as to increase the other’spayoff beyond one’s own, (Capraro et al. [2014b] and hyper-altruism(i.e., weighting the other’s payoff more than one’s own, (Crockett etal. [2014], Capraro [2015]). More generally, it is likely that this“deontological domain” extends what Peysakhovich et al. [2014] call‘cooperative phenotype’. In other words, one possible interpretationof our results is that the ‘cooperative phenotype’ extends beyondsocial dilemmas and regards also truth-telling when lying is Paretooptimal and lying when it is costly for the liar, but benefits theother person.

Additionally, our results connect to the work of Levine and Schweitzer [2015], which reported that telling white lies (both altruistic and Pareto optimal) signals prosocial tendencies in observers: third parties, when playing in the role of trusters in the Trust Game, allocate more money to people who have told a white lie in a previous Deception Game than to those who have told the truth. However, Levine and Schweitzer [2015] did not measure trustee’s behavior and so it remained unclear whether people telling a white lie were really more prosocial than those telling the truth. Our results provide evidence that this is true in the case of altruistic white lies, but false in the case of Pareto white lies. Further research may shed light on the origin of this false belief.

Finally, our results add to the literature regarding gender differences in deceptive behaviour. Dreber and Johannesson [2008] found that men were more likely than women to tell black lies (e.g., lies that increase the liar’s benefit at the expense of the listener). A similar result was shown by Friesen and Gangadharan [2012], who found that men are more likely than women to behave dishonestly for their own benefit. Yet, Childs [2012] failed to replicate this gender effect using a very similar design to that in Dreber and Johannesson [2008]. In the context of white lies, Erat and Gneezy [2012] reported that women are more likely than men to tell an altruistic white lie, but men are more likely than women to tell a Pareto white lie. This latter result was not replicated by Cappelen et al. [2013], who found no gender differences in telling a Pareto white lie. In line with the latter result, our results also show no gender difference in telling a Pareto white lie. But, interestingly, we found gender differences in telling an altruistic white lie, but in the opposite direction than that reported in Erat and Gneezy [2012]: we found that men are more likely than women to tell an altruistic white lie. Taken together, these results suggest that it may be premature to draw general conclusions about whether there are general gender differences in lying, and call for further studies.

References

Abeler, J., Becker, A., and Falk, A. (2014). Representative evidence on lying cost. Journal of Public Economics, 113:96--104.[bib]
Andreoni, J. and Vesterlund, L. (2001). Which is the fair sex? gender differences in altruism. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 116:293--312.[bib]
Bartneck, C., Duenser, A., Moltchanova, E., and Zawieska, K. (2015). Comparing the similarity of responses received from studies in amazon's mechanical turk to studies conducted online and with direct recruitment. PLoS ONE, 10:e0121595.[bib]
Blackburn, S. (2003). Ethics: A very short introduction. Oxford University Press.[bib]
Bolton, G.E. and Katok, E. (1995). An experimental test for gender differences in beneficent behaviour. Economics Letters, 18:287--292.[bib]
Bolton, G.E. and Ockenfels, A. (2000). A theory of equity, reciprocity and competition. The American Economic Review, 90:166--193.[bib]
Camerer, C. (2003). Behavioral game theory. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.[bib]
Cappelen, A., Sørensen, E., and Tungodden, B. (2013). When do we lie? Journal of Economic Behavior & Organizations, 93:258--265.[bib]
Capraro, V. (2013). A model of human cooperation in social dilemmas. PLoS ONE, 8:e72427.[bib]
Capraro, V. (2015). The emergence of hyper-altruistic behaviour in conflictual situations. Scientific Reports, 4:9916.[bib]
Capraro, V., Jordan, J.J., and Rand, D.G. (2014a). Heuristics guide the implementation of social preferences in one-shot prisoner's dilemma experiments. Scientific Reports, 4:6790.[bib]
Capraro, V. and Marcelletti, A. (2014). Do good actions inspire good actions in others? Scientific Reports, 4:7470.[bib]
Capraro, V., Smyth, C., Mylona, K., and Niblo, G.A. (2014b). Benevolent characteristics promote cooperative behaviour among humans. PLoS ONE, 9:e102881.[bib]
Charness, G. and Rabin, M. (2002). Understanding social preferences with simple tests. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 117:817--869.[bib]
Childs, J. (2012). Gender differences in lying. Economics Letters, 114:147--149.[bib]
Cohen, T.R., Gunia, B.C., Kim-Jun, S.Y., and Murnighan, J.K. (2009). Do groups lie more than individuals? honesty and deception as a function of strategic self-interest. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 45:1321--1324.[bib]
Conrads, J., Irlenbusch, B., Rilke, R.M., and Walkowitz, G. (2013). Lying and team incentives. Journal of Economic Psychology, 34:1--7.[bib]
Crockett, M.J., Kurth-Nelson, Z., Siegel, J.Z., Dayan, P., and Dolan, R.J. (2014). Harm to others outweighs harm to self in moral decision making. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA, 111:17320--17325.[bib]
Croson, R. and Gneezy, U. (2009). Gender differences in preferences. Journal of Economic Literature, 47:1--27.[bib]
Dreber, A., Ellingsen, T., Johannesson, M., and Rand, D.G. (2013). Do people care about social context? framing effects in dictator games. Experimental Economics, 16:349--371.[bib]
Dreber, A. and Johannesson, M. (2008). Gender differences in deception. Economics Letters, 99:197--199.[bib]
Dreber, A., von Essen, E., and Ranehill, E. (2014). Gender and competition in adolescence: task matters. Experimental Economics, 17:154--172.[bib]
Dufwenberg, M. and Muren, A. (2006). Gender composition in teams. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 61:50--54.[bib]
Eckel, C.C. and Grossmann, P. (1997). Are women less selfish than men? evidence from dictator experiments. Economic Journal, 107:726--735.[bib]
Engel, C. (2011). Dictator games: A meta-study. Experimental Economics, 14:583--610.[bib]
Erat, S. and Gneezy, U. (2012). White lies. Management Science, 58:723--733.[bib]
Fehr, E. and Schmidt, K. (1999). A theory of fairness, competition and cooperation. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 114:817--868.[bib]
Forsythe, R., Horowitz, J.L., Savin, N.E., and Sefton, M. (1994). Fairness in simple bargaining experiments. Games and Economic Behavior, 6:347--369.[bib]
Friesen, L. and Gangadharan, L. (2012). Individual level evidence of dishonesty and the gender effect. Economics Letters, 117:624--626.[bib]
Gino, F., Ayal, S., and Ariely, D. (2013). Self-serving altruism? the lure of unethical actions that benefit others. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 93:285--292.[bib]
Gneezy, U. (2005). Deception: The role of consequences. American Economic Review, 95:384--394.[bib]
Gneezy, U., Rockenbach, B., and Serra-Garcia, M. (2013). Measuring lying aversion. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 93:293--300.[bib]
Horton, J.J., Rand, D.G., and Zeckhauser, R.J. (2011). The online laboratory: Conducting experiments in a real labor market. Experimental Economics, 14:399--425.[bib]
Houser, D. and Schunk, D. (2009). Fairness, competition, and gender: Evidence from german schoolchildren. Journal of Economic Psychology, 30:634--641.[bib]
Hurkens, S. and Kartik, N. (2009). Would i lie to you? on social preferences and lying aversion. Experimental Economics, 12:180--192.[bib]
Kahneman, D., Knetsch, J.L., and Thaler, R.H. (1986). Fairness and the assumptions of economics. Journal of Business, 59:S285--S300.[bib]
Kant, I. (1996). The Metaphysics of Morals. Cambridge UK: Cambridge University Press.[bib]
Levine, E.E. and Schweitzer, M. (2014). Are liars ethical? on the tension between benevolence and honesty. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 53:107--117.[bib]
Levine, E.E. and Schweitzer, M. (2015). Prosocial lies: When deception breeds trust. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 26:88--106.[bib]
López-Pérez, R. and Spiegelman, E. (2013). Why do people tell the truth? experimental evidence for pure lie aversion. Experimental Economics, 16:233--247.[bib]
Lundquist, T., Ellingsen, T., Gribbe, E., and Johannesson, M. (2009). The aversion to lying. Journal ofEconomic Behavior & Organization, 70:81--92.[bib]
Paolacci, G., Chandler, J., and Ipeirotis, P.G. (2010). Running experiments on amazon mechanical turk. Judgment and Decision Making, 5:411--419.[bib]
Peysakhovich, A., Nowak, M.A., and Rand, D.G. (2014). Humans display a `cooperative phenotype' that is domain general and temporally stable. Nature Communications, 5:4939.[bib]
Plato (1997). Republic, Complete Works (997--1223). Indianapolis, Indiana: Hackett Publishing Company.[bib]
Rapoport, A. (1965). Prisoner's Dilemma: A Study in Conflict and Cooperation. University of Michigan Press.[bib]
Shalvi, S., Dana, J., Handgraaf, M. J.J., and deDreu, C. K.W. (2011). Justified ethicality: Observing desired counterfactuals modifies ethical perceptions and behavior. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 115:181--190.[bib]
Shalvi, S. and deDreu, C. K.W. (2014). Oxytocin promotes group-serving dishonesty. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA, 111:5503--5507.[bib]
Weisel, O. and Shalvi, S. (2015). The collaborative roots of corruption. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA, 112:10651--10656.[bib]
Wiltermuth, S.S. (2011). Cheating more when the spoils are split. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 115:157--168.[bib]

This file was generated bybibtex2html 1.98.

Appendix: Experimental instructions

4.1Deception Game: Altruistic White Lies treatment

Please read these instructions carefully. You may earn a considerable sum of money, depending on the decisions you make in the experiment.

You have been matched with another participant. Your bonus and that of the other participant depends only on your choice. The other participant does not play any active role.

There are two groups (group 1, group 2). You will be randomly assigned to one of them. You will be informed of the group you have been assigned to, but the other participant will not.

We will ask you to declare the group you have been assigned to. So you get to choose between two possible options:

  • Option 1: I have been assigned to group 1.
  • Option 2: I have been assigned to group 2.

If you choose the option corresponding to the number of the actual group you have been assigned to, then you will receive 10c and the other participant will receive 10c.

If you choose the option correponding to the number of the other group (the one you have not been assigned to), then you will receive 9c and the other participant will receive 30c.

Finally, only you will be informed of the particular monetary value connected to each message. The other participant will not be informed of these monetary values.

Here are some questions to ascertain that you understand the rules. Remember that you have to answer all of these questions correctly in order to get the completion code. If you fail any of them, the survey will automatically end and you will not get any payment.

What is the choice that maximise YOUR outcome? Available answers: Choosing the message corresponding to the number of the actual group you have been assigned to/Choosing the message corresponding to the number of the other group (the one you have not been assigned to).

What is the choice that maximise the OTHER PARTICIPANT’S outcome? Available aswers: Choosing the message corresponding to the number of the actual group you have been assigned to/Choosing the message corresponding to the number of the other group (the one you have not been assigned to).

Congratulations, you have passed all comprehension questions. It is time to make your real choice.

Here participants were randomly divided in two conditions, corresponding to the two possible groups. We report the instructions only for Group 1.

You have been assigned to group 1.

Which option do you choose?

4.2Deception Game: Pareto White Lies treatment

Please read these instructions carefully. You may earn a considerable sum of money, depending on the decisions you make in the experiment.

You have been matched with another participant. Your bonus and that of the other participant depends only on your choice. The other participant does not play any active role.

There are two groups (group 1, group 2). You will be randomly assigned to one of them. You will be informed of the group you have been assigned to, but the other participant will not.

We will ask you to declare the group you have been assigned to. So you get to choose between two possible options:

  • Option 1: I have been assigned to group 1.
  • Option 2: I have been assigned to group 2.

If you choose the option corresponding to the number of the actual group you have been assigned to, then you will receive 10c and the other participant will receive 10c.

If you choose the option correponding to the number of the other group (the one you have not been assigned to), then you will receive 15c and the other participant will receive 15c.

Finally, only you will be informed of the particular monetary value connected to each message. The other participant will not be informed of these monetary values.

Here are some questions to ascertain that you understand the rules. Remember that you have to answer all of these questions correctly in order to get the completion code. If you fail any of them, the survey will automatically end and you will not get any payment.

What is the choice that maximise YOUR outcome? Available aswers: Choosing the message corresponding to the number of the actual group you have been assigned to/Choosing the message corresponding to the number of the other group (the one you have not been assigned to).

What is the choice that maximise the OTHER PARTICIPANT’S outcome? Available aswers: Choosing the message corresponding to the number of the actual group you have been assigned to/Choosing the message corresponding to the number of the other group (the one you have not been assigned to).

Congratulations, you have passed all comprehension questions. It is time to make your real choice.

Here participants were randomly divided in two conditions, corresponding to the two possible groups. We report the instructions only for Group 1.

You have been assigned to group 1.

Which option do you choose?

4.3Dictator Game

Please read these instructions carefully. You may earn a considerable sum of money, depending on the decisions you make in the experiment.

You have been paired with another participant. The amount of money you can earn depends only on your choice.

You are given 20c and the other participant is given nothing.

You have to decide how much, if any, to transfer to the other participant.

The other participant has no choice, is REAL, and will really accept the amount of money you decide to transfer.

No deception is used. You will really get the amount of money you decide to keep.

Here are some questions to ascertain that you understand the rules. Remember that you have to answer all of these questions correctly in order to get the completion code. If you fail any of them, the survey will automatically end and you will not get any payment.

What is the transfer by you that maximizes your bonus? Available aswers: 0c/2c/4c/.../20c.

What is the transfer by you that maximizes the other participant’s bonus? Available aswers: 0c/2c/4c/.../20c.

Congratulations, you have answered both comprehension questions correctly!

It is now time to make your choice.

What amount will you transfer to the other person? Available options: 0c/2c/4c/.../20c.

4.4Prisoner’s Dilemma

Please read these instructions carefully. You may earn a considerable sum of money, depending on the decisions you make in the experiment.

You have been paired with another anonymous participant. You are both given 10c and each of you must decide whether to transfer the 10c or not. Each time a participant transfers their 10c, the other participant earns 20c.

So:

  • If you both decide to transfer the 10c, you end the game with 20c
  • If the other participant transfers the 10c and you do not, you end the game with 30c
  • If you transfer the 10c and the other participant does not, you end the game with 0c
  • If neither of you transfer the 10c, then you end the game with 10c

Here are some questions to ascertain that you understand the rules. Remember that you have to answer all of these questions correctly in order to get the completion code. If you fail any of them, the survey will automatically end and you will not get any payment.

What choice should you make to maximise your gain? Available aswers: Transfer the 10c/Do not tranfer the 10c.

What choice should you make to maximise the other participant’s gain? Available aswers: Transfer the 10c/Do not tranfer the 10c.

What choice should the other participant make to maximise your gain? Available aswers: Transfer the 10c/Do not tranfer the 10c.

What choice should the other participant make to maximise their gain? Available aswers: Transfer the 10c/Do not tranfer the 10c.

Congratulations, you have answered both comprehension questions correctly!

It is now time to make your choice. Available options: Tranfer the 10c/Do not trasfer the 10c

Regression tables

Table 1: Summary of the statistical analysis regarding the Dictator Game. Weran linear regression predicting DG donation. The explanatory variableAWL (resp. PWL) takes value 0 if a subject lied inthe AWL (resp. PWL) treatment, and value 1 otherwise. The explanatoryvariable sex takes value 1 (resp. 2) if a subject is a man(resp. woman). We report coefficient, standard error (in brackets,below the coefficient), and significance levels using the notation: * p<0.1, ** p<0.01, and *** p<0.001.

IIIIIIIVVVI
AWL-1.14*-1.33*
(0.61)(0.60)
PWL1.43*1.26*
(0.68)(0.67)
sex1.63**1.74***1.87***1.80***
(0.51)(0.51)(0.53)(0.53)
age0.03-0.03-0.030.03
(0.02)(0.02)(0.02)(0.02)
education0.010.010.070.11
(0.21)(0.21)(0.21)(0.21)
constant5.10***0.611.544.31***0.580.31
(0.54)(1.38)(0.28)(0.29)(1.39)(1.39)
No. cases357357357340340340

Table 2: Summary of the statistical analysis regarding the Prisoner’sDilemma. We ran logit regression predicting PD cooperation (0 =defection, 1 = cooperation). The explanatory variable

AWL(resp. PWL) takes value 0 if a subject lied in the AWL(resp. PWL) treatment, and value 1 otherwise. The explanatory variablesex takes value 1 (resp. 2) if a subject is a man(resp. woman). We report coefficient, standard error (in brackets,below the coefficient), and significance levels using the notation: * p<0.1, ** p<0.01, and *** p<0.001.

IIIIIIIVVVI
AWL-1.25***-1.31***
(0.30)(0.31)
PWL0.70*0.78*
(0.34)(0.35)
sex0.030.140.45*0.46*
(0.28)(0.29)(0.26)(0.27)
age0.01-0.01-0.010.01
(0.01)(0.01)(0.01)(0.01)
education-0.14-0.160.080.10
(0.12)(0.12)(0.11)(0.12)
constant0.19-0.360.48-0.65-1.83*-2.17
(0.25)(0.63)(0.81)(0.14)(0.73)(0.76)
No. cases257257257258258258
*

Institute for Logic, Language, and Computation, Universiteit van Amsterdam, 1090 GE, Amsterdam, The Netherlands.

#

Corresponding author. Center for Mathematics and Computer Science, 1098 XG, Amsterdam, The Netherlands. Emaial: V.Capraro@cwi.nl

Copyright: © 2015.The authors license this article under the terms of theCreative CommonsAttribution 3.0 License.

1

The fact that womengive more than men in the DG is reasonably well established, as themajority of studies report either this effect Eckel andGrossmann [1997], Andreoni and Vesterlund [2001], Dufwenberg andMuren [2006], Houser and Schunk [2009],Dreber et al. [2013],Dreberet al. [2014],Capraro and Marcelletti [2014],Capraro [2015] or anull effect (e.g., Dreber et al. [2013],Bolton and Katok[1995]). Also the fact that older people donate more than youngerpeople is relatively well established (see Engel [2011] for ameta-analysis and Capraro and Marcelletti [2014] for a replicationof this effect on an AMT sample).

This document was translated from LATEX byHEVEA.
Does telling white lies signal pro-social preferences? (2024)

References

Top Articles
Latest Posts
Article information

Author: Domingo Moore

Last Updated:

Views: 5580

Rating: 4.2 / 5 (73 voted)

Reviews: 88% of readers found this page helpful

Author information

Name: Domingo Moore

Birthday: 1997-05-20

Address: 6485 Kohler Route, Antonioton, VT 77375-0299

Phone: +3213869077934

Job: Sales Analyst

Hobby: Kayaking, Roller skating, Cabaret, Rugby, Homebrewing, Creative writing, amateur radio

Introduction: My name is Domingo Moore, I am a attractive, gorgeous, funny, jolly, spotless, nice, fantastic person who loves writing and wants to share my knowledge and understanding with you.